Women are the equals of men and should be treated as such.
For most people, the foregoing statement is the core of what
feminism means. But what is equal? How is equality defined?
For example, does it mean equality under existing laws and
equal representation in existing institutions? Or does it
involve a socio-economic equality -- a redistribution of wealth
and power -- that, in turn, requires new laws and an overturning
of existing institutions. It could involve cultural equality by
which women are accorded the same level of respect as men with
sexual harassment laws, for example, enforcing that respect.
The manner in which the word "equality" is defined is a
litmus test by which different schools of feminism can be
distinguished from each other.
Throughout the 19th century, the mainstream of American
feminism defined "equality" as equal treatment with men under
existing laws and equal representation within existing
institutions. More revolutionary feminists protested that the
existing laws and institutions were the source of injustice and,
as such, could not be reformed. The system had to be swept away
before women's rights could be secured.
In simplistic terms, the two more revolutionary traditions
were socialist feminism, from which contemporary radical
feminism draws heavily, and individualist feminism, which is
sometimes called libertarian feminism. These two traditions
differed dramatically in their approaches to equality.
To socialist feminism, equality was a socioeconomic term.
Women could be equal only after private property and the
economic relationships it encouraged -- that is, capitalism --
were eliminated. Equality was also a cultural goal. The 19th
century parallel to the 20th century rebellion against 'white
male culture' -- against pornography, for example -- is to be
found in the 19th century social purity crusades over such
issues as temperance. The social purity campaigns attempted to
impose 'virtue'-- that is, to impose a morally proper behavior
upon society through the force of law -- in much the same way
that modern feminism attempts to impose political
correctness.
To individualist feminism, equality was achieved when the
individual rights of women were fully acknowledged under laws
that identically protected the person and property of men and
women. It made no reference to being economically or socially
equal, only to equal treatment under the laws that governed
society in such a manner as to protect person and property.
In an ideal society, the legal system would make no
distinction based upon secondary characteristics, such as sex,
but would protect the rights each individual equally. Women
would neither be oppressed by nor receive any privileges under
the law. This society does not exist. As long as the law
distinguishes between the sexes, women need to stand up and
demand their full and equal rights. No more, no less. This
demand forms the political crux of individualist feminism.
This article focuses on the two revolutionary forms of
feminism, which are diametrically opposite to each other
ideologically and define the two extremes of feminism: radical
feminism and individualist feminism.
Speaking in 20th century terms, how do they define equality?
For radical feminism, equality is socio-economic and cultural.
That is, the class distinctions between the genders must be
eliminated so that men and women can enjoy social, economic,
political and sexual parity. To achieve this, it is necessary to
sweep away patriarchy, which is a combination of white male
culture and capitalism.
For individualist feminism, equality still means equal
treatment of men and women under laws that protect person and
property. Individualist feminism says nothing about whether the
resulting wealth should be spread equally between the sexes.
That kind of division could only be achieved through the
imposition of law, through State intervention over people's
lives and property. This is precisely what individualist
feminism opposes -- the use of force in society.
Let me provide an example of why this last statement is as
revolutionary. Consider the issue of marriage. Mainstream
feminism says, "Reform divorce laws to make them just."
Individualist feminism says, "the very existence of
marriage/divorce laws is an injustice because the State has no
proper authority over what should be a private contract between
individuals."
The word "just" has appeared. Briefly, I want to consider how
the two forms of feminism approach the concept of justice.
Radical feminism approaches justice as an end state; by which
I mean, it provides a specific picture of what constitutes a
just society. A just society would be one without patriarchy or
capitalism in which the socio-economic and cultural equality of
women was fully expressed. In other words, justice is a specific
end state in which society embodies specific economic, political
and cultural arrangements. It says employers shall pay men and
women equally, no one should publish pornography, sexual
comments in the workplace must be outlawed.
By contrast, the individualist feminist approach to justice
is means-oriented: that is it refers primarily to methodology.
The methodology is "anything that is peaceful." The only
end-state individualist feminism envisions is the protection of
person and property -- that is, the removal of force and fraud
from society.
Otherwise stated, justice is not embodied in a specifically
defined end-state: whatever society results from the free and
peaceful choices of individuals are,
politically-speaking, a just society. Aspects of the
society may not be moral and individualist feminists may use
education, protest, boycott, and moral suasion -- the whole
slate of persuasive strategies -- to affect change. What they
will not do is use force in the form of government law to
restrict peaceful choices.
The conflicting concepts of justice between radical and
individualist feminism highlight one of the key differences in
their approach to social problems: namely, the willingness of
socialist or radical feminists to use the State. This difference
is not surprising when you realize that the radical feminist
ideal of justice *can* by established by the use of force, by
the State. You can, for example, impose a specific economic
arrangement on society. You can arrest people for over-charging
or for bad hiring practices. But you cannot use force to impose
a purely voluntary society: it is a contradiction in terms.
Leaving theory, I want to provide a sense of the unique
history of individualist feminism within America.
As an organized force, feminism can be dated from the
abolitionist movement that arose in the early 1830s. And the two
dominant ideological influences on the feminism that arose were
Quakerism and individualism. Many courageous women advanced the
status of women prior to that date. For example, in the 17th
century, Anne Hutchinson led the first organized attack on the
Puritan orthodoxy of the Massachusetts Bay Colony. But these
women spoke out as individuals rather than as part of a
self-conscious movement dedicated to women's rights.
Abolitionism was the radical anti-slavery movement that
demanded the immediate cessation of slavery on the grounds that
every human being was a self-owner: every human being had a
moral jurisdiction over his or her own body.
Gradually, abolitionist women began to apply the principle of
self-ownership to themselves. The abolitionist feminist Abbie
Kelley observed: "We have good cause to be grateful to the
slave, for the benefit we have received to ourselves, in working
for him. In striving to strike his irons off, we found most
surely that we were manacled ourselves."
Within abolitionism, women's rights stirred hot debate.
Perhaps the strongest advocate of women's rights was the
libertarian William Lloyd Garrison, editor of the Liberator, who
insisted that anti-slavery was a battle for human rights, not
male rights.
Then, a watershed event occurred: the 1840 World Anti-Slavery
Conference in London, England. The abolitionist feminism
Elizabeth Cady Stanton, who attended the 1840 World Anti-Slavery
Conference in London, was embittered by the dismissive treatment
women received from the less-enlightened Englishmen. Garrison,
who also attended, had been so outraged that he withdrew from
the floor to the curtained off section to which the women were
relegated.
Later, with the Quaker Lucretia Mott, Stanton planned the
1848 Seneca Falls Convention to discuss women's rights. There,
women's suffrage resolution was introduced: "Resolved, that it
is the duty of the women of this country to secure to themselves
their sacred right to the elective franchise." The resolution
met strong resistance from Mott and other members of the old
guard of abolitionist feminists who were deeply opposed to using
government to solve social problems. But it passed.
Unfortunately for the American individualist tradition -- in
all its manifestations -- the Civil War erupted. If 'War is the
health of state', as Randolph Bourne claimed, then it is the
death of individualism. There are many reasons for this; one of
them being that individualism is, at its roots, an anti-Statist
ideology, and war involves an increase in State power that never
seems to roll back to its prewar level when peace is declared.
After the war, the key issue for feminism became the
Constitution; women wished to be included in the wording of the
Fourteenth and Fifteenth Amendments that aimed at securing
freedom for blacks. The Fourteenth Amendment introduced the word
"male" into the United States Constitution. The Fifteenth
Amendment assured that the right to vote could not be abridged
because of "race, color, or previous condition of servitude." It
made no reference to sex. The abolitionist women felt betrayed.
Susan B. Anthony wrote, "We repudiated man's counsels forever."
This became a pivotal point at which mainstream feminism became
alienated from men.
At this juncture, the feminist movement diversified, with the
mainstream focusing its efforts into a drive for woman's
suffrage. Other feminists were suspicious of political solutions
to social problems.
Individualist feminism found expression within a variety of
social movements, especially free love, free thought, and
individualist anarchism. There, these feminists functioned as a
radical segment, where they represented and pursued the
interests of women.
The most important vehicle was the free love movement that
sought to separate the State from sexual matters such as
marriage, adultery, divorce, and birth control. Free love
demanded that such matters be left to the conscience and
contracts of those involved. Consider free love, very briefly...
In 1889, a woman who had just risked her life in a
self-induced abortion wrote to the libertarian periodical,
Lucifer the Light Bearer, pleading:
"I know I am dreadful wicked, but I am sure to be in the
condition from which I risked my life to be free, and I cannot
stand it...Would you know of any appliance that will prevent
conception? If there is anything reliable, you will save my life
by telling me of it."
The woman wrote to Lucifer -- published and edited by Moses
Harman -- because, in the late 1800s, it was one of the few
forums openly promoting birth control. Moses Harman insisted
that woman's self-ownership fully acknowledged in all sexual
arrangements.
Unfortunately, Harman ran counter to the Comstock Act (1873),
which prohibited the mailing of obscene matter but did not
define what constituted obscenity. Whatever it was, it
specifically included contraceptives and birth control
information. A witchhunt ensued.
Against this backdrop, Harman began his "free word" policy by
which he refused to edit correspondence to Lucifer that
contained explicit language. Harman maintained, "Words are not
deeds, and it is not the province of civil law to take
preventative measures against remote or possible consequences of
words, no matter how violent or incendiary." He openly discussed
birth control.
In 1887, the staff of Lucifer was arrested for the
publication of three letters and indicted on 270 counts of
obscenity. One letter had described the plight of a woman whose
husband forced sex upon her even though it tore the stitches
from a recent operation. It is a very early analysis of forced
sex within marriage constituting rape.
Harman's legal battles against the Comstock laws continued
from 1887 through to 1906, his last imprisonment during which he
spent a year at hard labor, often breaking rocks for eight hours
a day in the Illinois snow. Harman was 75 at the time."
Interestingly, when the authorities came to arrest Harman in
1887, his 16-year old daughter Lillian was not present. She was
in jail herself, having been arrested for engaging in a private
marriage -- that is, a marriage that consisted of a private
contract, without Church or State involvement. At that ceremony,
Moses had refused to give his daughter away, stating that she
was the owner of her person.
The Harman episode is not a tale of individualist feminism
because he championed birth control. A number of traditions did
that. Harman was an individualist feminist because of the
ideology and methodology he used. He based his arguments on
women's self-ownership and extended this principle to all
arrangements, sexual and economic. He refused to use the State
in personal relationships because he considered it to be the
institutionalization of force in society. He actively opposed
laws that restricted peaceful behavior.
Moses Harman -- along with Voltairine de Cleyre -- are the
most prominent figures from the 19th century. In their own time,
such figures as Harman were well recognized by contemporary
radicals. Emma Goldman in her autobiography "Living My Life"
credited him with being a pioneer who made her birth control
work possible. In 1907, when George Bernard Shaw was asked why
he did not tour America, he replied if the "brigands" could
imprison Moses Harman for expressing basically the same views
set forth in his play Man and Superman he did not care to
come to America and test his luck. It is a travesty that he is
forgotten today.
So with a small taste of history, let's move back to
theory.
Arguably, the most important concept in feminism today is
"class." There are men, there are women, they are separate
classes...or so the theory goes.
The foregoing statement is different than the tradition "war
between the sexes." That war refers to the fact that, in the
same circumstances, men and women often want different things
and, so, come into conflict. For example, on a date men are
typically said to want sex whereas women are said to seek a
relationship. This is not the conflict to which I am referring.
I am talking about a war of the gender.
A class is nothing more than an arbitrary grouping of
entities that share common characteristics as determined from a
certain epistemological point of view. In short, what
constitutes a class is defined by the purposes of the definer.
For example, a researcher studying drug addiction may break
society into classes of drug using and non-drug using people.
Classes can be defined by almost any factor salient to the
definer.
For radical feminists, gender is the salient factor. Many
fields of endeavor use biology as a dividing line. For example,
medicine often separates the sexes in order to apply different
medical treatment and techniques. Women are examined for breast
cancer and men for prostate problems. But medicine does not
claim that the basic interests of men and women as human beings
conflict or even diverge. The sexes share a basic biology that
requires the same approach of nutrition, exercise and common
sense lifestyle choices. In short, although the biology of the
sexes differs, they share the same goal of good health, which
can be defined and pursued in roughly the same manner.
By contrast, radical feminism advocates a theory of
fundamental class conflict based on gender. It claims that males
not only share a biological identity but also a political and
social one. The political interests of men are in necessary
conflict with those of women.
The concept of class conflict is widely associated with Karl
Marx, who popularized it as a tool to predict the political
interests and social behavior of individuals. Once the class
affiliation of an individual was known, his or her behavior
became predictable. To Marx, the salient feature defining a
person's class was his relationship to the means of production:
was he a capitalist or a worker? This is a form of relational
class analysis that describes a class in terms of its
relationship to an institution.
Radical feminism has adapted this theory. Catherine MacKinnon
refers to the analysis as "post-Marxist." By this, she means
that radical feminism embraces many aspects of Marxism but
rejects its insistence that economic status, not gender, is the
salient political factor that determines a class. Thus, radical
feminism incorporates such Marxist/socialist ideas as "surplus
labor" through which one class is said to use the free market in
order to commit economic theft upon another class. (An example
of surplus labor in radical feminism is unsalaried housework.)
The classification 'male' becomes so significant that it
predicts and determines how the individuals within that class
will behave. Thus, radical feminists can level accusations of
"rapist" at non-violent men because they are beneficiaries of
'the rape culture' established by patriarchy.
To prevent the oppression of women, it is necessary to
deconstruct the institutions through men control women --
institutions such as the free market
This class analysis makes no sense within the framework of
individualist feminism that declares all human beings to have
the same political interests.
Individualism has a long and differing tradition of class
analysis. The salient factor by which people are categorized is
whether he or she uses force in society. Do they acquire wealth
or power through merit and productivity or do they use
aggression, often in the form of law, to appropriate wealth and
power from others? Expressed in the most basic form,
individualist feminism asks, "are you a member of the political
or productive class?" This, too, is a form of relational class
analysis because it asks, "What is your relationship to the
State?"
Individualist feminism class analysis does not predict the
behavior of individuals. Both men and women can use the
political means. An individual can change his or her class
affiliation at will, abandoning the use of force and adopting
the economic means instead. In short, classes within
individualist feminist analysis are fluid. This is not true of
radical feminist analysis that is based on biology. Within
radical feminism, classes are static.
This difference has many implications. One is that
individualist feminist class analysis offers no predictive
value. Just because an individual has been a member of the
political class in the past says nothing about whether he or she
will continue to be so in the future.
This fluidity has a further implication. Namely, there is no
necessary conflict between the genders. The fact that men have
oppressed women in the past says nothing about whether they will
oppress women in the future. Whether an individual man is an
oppressor or a friend depends on whether he uses the political
means and this is a matter of his conscious choice. Men are not
the enemy.
Conclusion
Radical and individualist feminism constitute the two
extremes of the feminist movement. One advocates state-control;
the other, self-control. One considers men to be the enemy; the
other embraces men as valued partners. But the most important
feature of the ideological divide is individualist feminism's
insistence on applying the radically personal principle "A
woman's body, a woman's right" across the board to all issues.